alexa Unital algebras of Hom-associative type and surjective or injective twistings | OMICS International
ISSN: 1736-4337
Journal of Generalized Lie Theory and Applications
Make the best use of Scientific Research and information from our 700+ peer reviewed, Open Access Journals that operates with the help of 50,000+ Editorial Board Members and esteemed reviewers and 1000+ Scientific associations in Medical, Clinical, Pharmaceutical, Engineering, Technology and Management Fields.
Meet Inspiring Speakers and Experts at our 3000+ Global Conferenceseries Events with over 600+ Conferences, 1200+ Symposiums and 1200+ Workshops on
Medical, Pharma, Engineering, Science, Technology and Business

Unital algebras of Hom-associative type and surjective or injective twistings

Yael FREGIER1*, Aron GOHR 1, and Sergei SILVESTROV 2

1Mathematics Research Unit, University of Luxembourg, 162A Avenue de la faiencerie, L-1511 Luxembourg, Grand-Duchy of Luxembourg

2Centre for Mathematical Sciences, Lund University, Box 118, SE-221 00 Lund, Sweden

E-mails: [email protected], [email protected], [email protected]

Received date: August 25, 2009, Revised date: October 29, 2009

Visit for more related articles at Journal of Generalized Lie Theory and Applications

Abstract

In this paper, we introduce a common generalizing framework for alternative types of Hom-associative algebras. We show that the observation that unital Hom-associative algebras with surjective or injective twisting map are already associative has a generalization in this new framework. We also show by construction of a counterexample that another such generalization fails even in a very restricted particular case. Finally, we discuss an application of these observations by answering in the negative the question whether nonassociative algebras with unit such as the octonions may be twisted by the composition trick into Hom-associative algebras.

Introduction

Hom-Lie-algebras were first studied in the context of deformation of Witt and Virasoro algebras by Hartwig, Larsson, and Silvestrov in [7]. The basic idea underlying Hom-algebras, which amounts to generalization of a given type of algebraic structure by adjoining as an additional piece of data linear maps twisting the defining identities, has since been applied in many categories of algebraic objects. In [7,8,12], quasi-Hom-Lie algebras, the general quasi-Lie algebras, and the corresponding generalization of Leibniz algebras quasi-Leibniz algebras [9] have been introduced. The graded versions, Γ-graded quasi-Lie algebras, were introduced in [10]. They contain Γ-graded quasi-Hom-Lie, Γ-graded Hom-Lie algebras, and graded quasi-Lie algebras of Witt type considered by Sigurdsson and Silvestrov in [11]. Recently, Ammar and Makhlouf [1] furthered this line of investigation by extending the main theorem from original paper by Hartwig, Larsson, and Silvestrov [7] to the Z2-graded case of Hom-Lie superalgebras. Also, Daniel Larsson has considered in [13] a modification of Hom-Lie algebras in connection to number theory and arithmetic geometry.

In the search of a counterpart of the associative algebras in the context of Hom-Lie algebras, Hom-associative algebras have been introduced by Makhlouf and Silvestrov in 2006 in [15], where it was shown that the commutator bracket of a Hom-associative algebra gives rise to a Hom-Lie algebra. Furthermore, in [15], a classification of Hom-Lie admissible algebras was established, Hom-Leibniz algebras, the subclass of quasi-Leibniz algebras, have been considered, notion of exibility was extended to Hom-algebras, and exible Hom-algebras have been characterized using Jordan and Lie parts of the multiplication. Also, in [15], a generalization of Hom-associative algebras, G-Hom-associative algebras, and their subclasses left symmetric Hom-algebras, Hom-pre-Lie algebras, or right symmetric Hom-algebras, and two other new classes of Hom-algebras have been introduced and G-Hom-associative algebras have been shown to be Hom-Lie admissible. The issue of constructing enveloping Homalgebra structures for Hom-Lie algebras has been considered by Yau in [19].

On the dual side, Hom-coalgebras, Hom-bialgabras, and Hom-Hopf algebras have been considered for the first time by Makhlouf and Silvestrov in [16] in 2007 and further studied by the same authors in [17] and also by Yau in [21]. Recently, Yau has continued this investigation in the direction of Hom-quantum groups in [22,23]. Also, in 2009, following the works of Makhlouf, Silvestrov, and Yau, Hom-Hopf algebras were put in a general framework of monoidal categories by Caenepeel and Goyvaerts [3]. At the same time, on the side of algebra structures, formal deformations and elements of co-homology for Hom-associative and Hom-Lie algebras have been considered by Makhlouf and Silvestrov in [18], and elements of homology for Hom-algebras have been considered by Yau in [20]. Also, recently, Ataguema, Makhlouf, and Silvestrov introduced Hom-Nambu and Hom-Nambu-Lie algebras and n-ary versions of Hom-associative algebras in [2], and Makhlouf introduced Hom-Jordan algebras in [14].

Hom-associative algebras have been a subject of recent intensive study due to their rich structure theory and the fact that constructions coming from their classical counterparts have been found to transfer to a meaningful extent. Also helpful in this context is the availability of computational tools which greatly facilitate the search for examples and the proof of equational theorems about Hom-associative structures. Finally, inspiration has come from other types of Hom-algebras such as Hom-Lie algebras.

It was first pointed out by Fregier and Gohr in [4] that in the process of defining a twisted notion of, for instance, associativity or the Jacobi identity, there are some choices left on where to apply the twisting. At least in the Hom-associative category it does not seem to be the case that only one of the choices leads to an interesting theory. In [4], this leads to a systematic study of alternative types of Hom-associative algebras. In [3], an attempt is made to identify a single \correct" set of definitions for the Hom-associative and eventually the Hom-Hopf settings by approaching the problem of defining these notions from a categorytheoretical point of view.

In this article, we provide a common framework unifying all the types of Hom-associative algebras previously considered and many more exotic ones. We show that there is significant structure theory even in the context of such a strongly generalized notion of associativity. Finally, we discuss how conversely a related natural conjecture fails even under a mild generalization of the ordinary notion of Hom-associativity.

Hom-associative algebras.

Hom-associative algebras were introduced in [15], motivated by the need to obtain replacement of associative algebras in the context of Hom-Lie algebras providing also further ways of construction of Hom-Lie algebras. In [4], a study of alternative notions of Hom-associativity was started, essentially focusing on ways to use a single twisting map several times on both sides of the defining identity, while trying to preserve its symmetry and without considering cases where high powers of the twisting map appear. As a background, we quote the following table from [4] which summarizes the types considered there:

equation

equation

equation

In this paper, when we talk about a Hom-associative structure (V, ✶, α) without specifying anything else, we mean that (V, ✶, α) is Hom-associative in the usual sense, i.e., the binary operation satisfies the ordinary α-twisted associativity relation α(x) ✶ (y ✶ z) = (x ✶ y) ✶α(z): Linearity of any of the maps is regularly implied only when a module structure is given on V .

For precision of terminology, we repeat from [4] the following general definition associated with the Hom-associativity types. Here T denotes any of the types in the table quoted above.

Definition 2.1. A Hom-associative structure of type T is a triple (V, ✶, α) consisting of a set V equipped with a binary operation ✶ : V × VV and a map α : VV satisfying the Hom-associativity condition corresponding to type T. Here, T is understood to be one of the types in the table reproduced above.

Hom-rings and Hom-algebras are defined similarly, by imposing on α natural compatibility conditions, more specifically compatibility with the abelian group structure (A, +) in the case of Hom-rings and linearity in the case of Hom-algebras.

As observed in [4], without additional constraints these types of Hom-associative structures seem to not be closely linked to each other, i.e., as far as we know a structure may be of any type without being of any other. But with additional constraints one gets a nontrivial theory. In particular, as a possible constraint the property of having a unit element was considered in [4]. Under this condition, a partial ordering of types was obtained with the traditional type I1 ending up on top.

It should be noted however that in Hom-associative structures, several types of unitality make sense as was observed in [3,4,5,6]. Simultaneous investigation of the Hom-structures with various types of unitality is important and relations between the types in [4] are far less clear, e.g., in the case of weakly unital algebras.

In this paper we focus on the Hom-structures with the usual unitality condition, i.e., the existence of an element 1 in V such that 1 ✶ x = x ✶ 1 = x for all x in V . In the rest of the paper unless stated otherwise, we assume all Hom-structures to be unital in this usual sense.

We will now recall the definition of Hom-monoids and the short discussion of their relation to Hom-algebras as they were given in [4]. Our main motivation is the use of Hom-monoids in the construction of the counterexample of Section 5.

Definition 2.2. A Hom-monoid of type T is a Hom-associative structure of type T with unit.

There is a canonical way to associate to a Hom-associative algebra a Hom-monoid and to a Hom-monoid a Hom-associative algebra. We quote in this context the following example and remark from [4].

Example 2.3. Let (V, ✶,+, α, 1) be a Hom-algebra of type T. Then the multiplicative structure (V, ✶, α, 1) is a Hom-monoid also of type T.

Remark 2.4. Let k be a commutative ring and let equation be a Hom-monoid of type T. Let then V be the free k-module over S and define α : VV and ✶ : V × VV by linear extension of equation : S → S, respectively, equation : S × S → S to V . Then (V, ✶, α, 1) is a unital Hom-associative algebra of type T. We denote the Hom-algebra so constructed from a Hom-monoid S by k[S].

Sufficient conditions for associativity and hierarchy on types of unital Hom associative algebras

One of the first natural problems about Hom-associative algebras is to determine how close they are to being associative. The simplest form of this problem is to determine conditions under which a Hom-associative algebra is itself associative. This problem has been considered in [5] for unital Hom-associative algebras in the usual sense. For some of the types considered in [4], there exist obvious associativity criteria, sometimes even in the absence of unitality constraints. But for many of the nonstandard types it is not obvious whether the known answers for the ordinary type generalize.

The aim of this section is to give an overview of the answers known to this question in the case of a Hom-associative algebra of type I1 and recall the hierarchy among the diαerent types, in order to motivate our subsequent investigations.

We recall first the following proposition providing suocient conditions on the twisting map for a Hom-associative algebra to be associative [5].

Proposition 3.1. Let (V, ✶, α, 1) be a unital Hom-associative structure of type I1. Then the following hold.

(i) (V, ✶) is associative if α is surjective.

(ii) (V, ✶) is associative if α is injective.

(iii) If α is surjective, then α is also injective.

To finish our survey of results in this direction of associativity conditions for unital Homassociative structures, we remark that the condition of surjectivity can be relaxed for V a Hom-algebra over a field by introducing conditions on the codimension of Im(α) in V . For instance, dim(V/ Im(α)) = 1 is already suocient to force associativity. For details, we refer the reader to [5].

The hierarchy for the relations among Hom-associative types I and II can be summarized in the following proposition taken verbatim from [4].

Proposition 3.2. Let (V, ✶, 1, α) be unital structure, then one has the following relations between the Hom-associativity types satisfied by (V, ✶, 1, α):

(a) II1 ⇐ II ⇔ I1 ⇒ I3 ⇒ {I2, II2, II3 and II1},

(b) I2 ⇒ {II1 , II3}.

The point of recalling this hierarchy is that in a general theory for associativity conditions similar to the ones surveyed in the original type we will expect counterexamples to appear with greater likelihood in the lower levels of the hierarchy, since these are the least restricted. On the other hand, if we can find counterexamples to certain conjectures in the higher levels of the hierarchy, we know immediately that the conjecture in question is wrong for all types below. For instance, we will show in Section 5 that unital Hom-associative algebras of type I3 are not necessarily associative if they have an injective twisting map. By this we will immediately know that the same counterexample works for any types which in terms of the hierarchy are more general.

The next section is devoted to the extension of Proposition 3.1 in a generalized framework which encompasses all of these types. But one has to be very careful in which sense this proposition is extended. For example, Proposition 3.1(ii) is false in the case of type I3 as is shown by the counterexample given in the last section of this article.

Generalized Hom-associative structures and automatic associativity conditions

In this section, we introduce generalized Hom-associative structures that are built using several twisting maps and in particular include all types of Hom-associative structures discussed so far. For unital generalized Hom-structures we obtain in Theorem 4.2 suocient conditions for associativity, generalizing Proposition 3.1.

Definition 4.1. A generalized Hom-associative structure is a tuple (V, ✶, α1, α2, α3, α4, α5) consisting of a set V , a binary operation ✶ : V × VV and five maps αj : VV , j = 1, : : : , 5, such that

equation

Theorem 4.2. If a generalized Hom-structure (V, ✶, α1, α2, α3, α4, α5) has a unit element and if α1, α3, α4 are surjective and α2, α5 are injective, then (V, ✶) is associative.

The following corollary is one of the motivating applications of Theorem 4.2.

Corollary 4.3. If (V, ✶) is a nonassociative unital algebra, then the α-twisted product

x o y := α(x ✶ y)

cannot be Hom-associative if the twisting map α is bijective.

Proof of Corollary 4.3. Hom-associativity for o rewritten in terms of ✶ is

equation

which coincides with (4.1) when α3 = α4 = idV and α1 = α2 = α5 = α. If α is bijective, then equivalently it is both surjective and injective, and hence (V, ✶) must be associative by Theorem 4.2 in contradiction with the assumption of nonassociativity.

In particular, this shows that the octonions do not admit a bijective twisting into a Homassociative algebra since they are unital and nonassociative.

The proof of Theorem 4.2 is more complicated and is based on several lemmas. First of all note that under the condition of injectivity of α5 in Theorem 4.2 the identity (4.1) can be rewritten equivalently without α5 as

equation

In Theorem 4.2, the maps α1, α3, α4 are assumed to be surjective. In the sequel we choose some right-inverses β1, β3, β4 of α1, α3, α4, respectively, (αj o βj = idV ). Also, since α2 is assumed to be injective, we can choose some left-inverse β2 of α2, that is, β2 o α2 = idV .

Using α3 o β3 = idV , the map α3 can be removed from the generalized Hom-associativity axiom, which is thus equivalent to

equation

The following direct consequence of generalized Hom-associativity (4.3) can be easily proved using α1 o β1 = idV .

Lemma 4.4. Under conditions of Theorem 4.2, the following identity holds:

equation

By substitution of β1(x) in place of x, then using α1 o β1 = idV and finally setting y = 1 and z = 1 in (4.4), we get the following corollary.

Corollary 4.5.

equation

Lemma 4.6. Under conditions of Theorem 4.2, the following identity holds:

equation

Proof. By Corollary 4.5 and Lemma 4.4 with y = z = 1, we have

equation

which is equivalent to (4.6) by the assumption of injectivity of α2.

Lemma 4.7. Under conditions of Theorem 4.2, the following identity holds:

equation

Proof. The proof is obtained using (r.inv) the existence of a right inverse α1 o β1 = idV and generalized Hom-associativity as follows:

equation

Substitution of z = 1 into (4.7) leads to the following corollary.

Corollary 4.8. Under conditions of Theorem 4.2, the following identity holds:

equation

Putting x = 1 in (4.8) and then changing in the obtained identity letter y to letter x leads to the following corollary.

Corollary 4.9. Under conditions of Theorem 4.2, the following identity holds:

equation

The assumption that α2 is injective can be now applied to (4.9) to show that α41(1)) is in the center of (V, ✶), that is, commutes with any other element in V .

Corollary 4.10. Under conditions of Theorem 4.2, the following identity holds:

equation

Using (4.3) and α4 o β4 = idV we get also the following lemma.

Lemma 4.11. Under conditions of Theorem 4.2, the following identity holds:

equation

Proof. The proof is obtained using (4.3) and α4 o β4 = idV :

equation

Next lemma is obtained by combining (4.11), (4.9), (4.8), (4.6), and α4 o β4 = idV .

Lemma 4.12. Under conditions of Theorem 4.2, the following identity holds:

equation

Proof. The proof is as follows:

equation

The next lemma follows using (4.11), the generalized Hom-associativity (4.3), and α4 o β4 = idV .

Lemma 4.13. Under conditions of Theorem 4.2, the following identity holds:

equation

Proof. First of all,

equation

which is proved as follows:

equation

Substituting β4(z) in place of z in (4.14) we get

equation

Lemma 4.14. Under conditions of Theorem 4.2, the following identity holds:

equation

Proof. The identity

equation

can be proved as follows. Multiplying (4.9) on the right by y and then using the identity obtained by substituting (x, y, z) by (β1(1), x, y) in (4.4), one gets

equation

The proof can now be completed along the following lines:

equation

Finally, we are ready to proceed with the proof of the main Theorem 4.2.

Proof of Theorem 4.2. It suoces, by injectivity of α2, to prove that

equation

Let us start by replacing x by x ✶ y in (4.12):

equation

Thus, we get

equation

for the last equality we replaced y by y✶z in (4.12). By injectivity of α2 our result is equivalent to associativity.

Counterexample

We have seen that the observation that unital Hom-associative structures with surjective twisting map are associative has with Theorem 4.2 a counterpart in the generalized Homassociative setting. Looking at Theorem 4.2, it is natural to ask whether the surjectivity or injectivity assumptions on the αi may be varied. Can we possibly reach the same conclusions, for example, by assuming that α4 is injective and the other twisting maps are as in the theorem✶

In this section, we will answer this question in the negative. To understand why we take α4 instead of α1 for our first study of this kind of question, one should go back to the hierarchy of Hom-associative algebra types discussed in [4] and repeated in Section 2. Under the partial ordering of Hom-associativity conditions discussed there, in some sense the strongest condition apart from the original one was the type I3 condition. By Theorem 4.2, we know immediately that a unital type I3 Hom-associative structure is associative if the twisting map is surjective. We also know that in type I1 the condition of surjectivity of α can be replaced by injectivity. This makes it natural to ask if some similar replacement is possible in type I3. The rest of the section is devoted to the construction of a type I3 Hom-monoid which serves as a counterexample.

Let S be a set and let equation be the free magma with unit over S. Recall that equation can be realized by inductively defining in a first step a set equation consisting of the empty pair e, of pairs of elements in S, and finally of arbitrary pairs of elements of equation itself. In a second step, one introduces on this set an equivalence relationship generated by the relations (x, e) ~ (e, x) ~ x for all x ∈ equation. The set so obtained we call equation . Taking as magma multiplication then the pairforming operation, or more precisely to the operation induced by pair-forming on the level of equivalence classes of elements of equation, equation becomes the free magma with unit over S. Choosing then some c ∈ S, we can define a type I3 Hom-monoid by identifying also pairs in ~M which can be transformed into each other by a chain of relations of the form (x, c) ~ (c, x) for any x ∈ equation and (x, (y, z)) ~ ((x, y), z) for x, y, z ∈ equation and y a term containing c in at least one place. It is clear that the partition into equivalence classes induced by these relations on equation is compatible with pairing as product. We will denote by M the magma given by the set of equivalence classes on equation with the multiplication induced by pairing, i.e., x y := (x, y) for all x, y ∈ M. Define α : M → M by α(x) := (c, x). Then (M, , α) is a Hom-I3-monoid1.

Suppose now that S is a set with at least two elements. Then we can choose an s ∈ S such that s 6= c. None of the elementary transformations that we defined on equation to obtain M can be applied to (s, (s, s)) and ((s, s), s), respectively, showing that these two elements are diαerent in M and that therefore M is not associative.

If M is to supply a counterexample to the conjecture that for a Hom-monoid of type I3 injectivity of α implies associativity, we still need to prove that α, i.e., multiplication by c, is indeed injective on M.

To do this, we will first introduce some notation. For x ∈ M we say that x is c-free if c does not appear in x. It is clear that this is independent of choice of representative of x in equation. Also, we note that powers of c are well defined and therefore write cn to denote an n-fold product of c with itself irrespective of parenthesizing. Next, we realize that any x ∈ M can be written in the form

equation

with c-free xi. This is proven by induction on term structure. The base case, terms which are elements of S, is obvious. Now if we have (x, y) ∈ equation , we can by assumption find representations of x and y in the form

equation

with c-free xi. This is proven by induction on term structure. The base case, terms which are elements of S, is obvious. Now if we have (x, y) ∈ equation , we can by assumption find representations of x and y in the form

equation

and

equation

with c-free xi and yi. Now if r ≠ 0, we see that (x, y) itself is already in the claimed form. If on the other hand r 6= 0, we can use the fact that we have (uv)w = u(vw) whenever v is a term containing cr to see that

equation

Here, cr can still be drawn into the part of term corresponding to x. Since cr commutes with the xi, we can iterate this process until we reach the form

equation

We see now that this "normal form" is completely characterized by the exponent of c inside and the sequence x1, . . . . xm, y1, . . . , ys of c-free terms appearing afterwards. Noting that none of the admissible term rewriting rules allow one to change c-free subterms of a term, the order inside a term of c-free subterms, or the number of occurrences of c in the whole term, we conclude that this normal form is uniquely defined for each x ∈ M. But, the only eαect of multiplication by c on the normal form of an element of M is to raise the inner exponent by one. This is clearly a reversible operation, hence proving injectivity of multiplication by c.

Acknowledgements

This work was supported from the Swedish part by the Swedish Research Council, the Swedish Foundation for International Cooperation in Research and Higher Education (STINT), the Crafoord Foundation, the Royal Physiographic Society in Lund, and the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences. We want to gratefully acknowledge the support of the research grant R1F105L15 of the University of Luxembourg (Martin Schlichenmaier).

We also acknowledge the assistance from the first-order logic automatic deduction software Prover9 used by us when discovering the proofs in Section 4.

References

Select your language of interest to view the total content in your interested language
Post your comment

Share This Article

Relevant Topics

Recommended Conferences

Article Usage

  • Total views: 11928
  • [From(publication date):
    December-2009 - Sep 23, 2018]
  • Breakdown by view type
  • HTML page views : 8140
  • PDF downloads : 3788
 

Post your comment

captcha   Reload  Can't read the image? click here to refresh

Peer Reviewed Journals
 
Make the best use of Scientific Research and information from our 700 + peer reviewed, Open Access Journals
International Conferences 2018-19
 
Meet Inspiring Speakers and Experts at our 3000+ Global Annual Meetings

Contact Us

bornova escort

Datta A

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9037

Business & Management Journals

Ronald

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9042

Chemistry Journals

Gabriel Shaw

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9040

Clinical Journals

Datta A

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9037

Engineering Journals

James Franklin

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9042

Food & Nutrition Journals

Katie Wilson

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9042

General Science

Andrea Jason

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9043

Genetics & Molecular Biology Journals

Anna Melissa

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9006

Immunology & Microbiology Journals

David Gorantl

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9014

Materials Science Journals

Rachle Green

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9039

Nursing & Health Care Journals

Stephanie Skinner

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9039

Medical Journals

Nimmi Anna

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9038

Neuroscience & Psychology Journals

Nathan T

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9041

Pharmaceutical Sciences Journals

Ann Jose

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9007

Social & Political Science Journals

https://www.gaziantepescort.info

Steve Harry

[email protected]

1-702-714-7001Extn: 9042

 
© 2008- 2018 OMICS International - Open Access Publisher. Best viewed in Mozilla Firefox | Google Chrome | Above IE 7.0 version